An ordinal collapsing function (OCF for short) is a ordinal function which is studied together with an associated ordinal notation in proof theory. One of the characteristic feature of OCFs is that they output large ordinals using even larger ones, often uncountable ordinals. For example, Buchholz's OCF \(\psi\) satisfies \(\psi_0(\)\(\Omega\)\() = \varepsilon_0\) and \(\psi_0(\Omega_2) = \textrm{BHO}\), where \(\varepsilon_0\) denotes the least epsilon number and \(\textrm{BHO}\) denotes the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. In particular, an OCF gives a method of naming large countable ordinals using uncountable ordinals.

For the use of an OCF in googology, see also the description of OCFs and why they're needed. The most confusing fact on OCFs is that an OCF itself can never be an ordinal notation, although many googologists who do not know the precise definition of the notion of an ordinal notation state that OCFs are ordinal notations. An OCF is just a function defined in set theory, while an ordinal notation is a notation equipped with a primitive recursive well-ordering defined in arithmetic. In order to associate an ordinal notation to an OCF, we need to define a recurisve set of formal strings, a syntax on it as a first order language so that the notions of a term and a function symbol makes sense, a "structure" of the language whose underlying set consists of ordinals such that the interpretation of some function symbol is given by the OCF, and construct a primitive recursive relation encoding the \(\in\)-relation for ordinals restricted to the underlying set of the structure.

To create an associated ordinal notation is much more difficult than to create an OCF. Therefore stating something like "I created an ordinal notation" just by creating an OCF does not literally make sense. Actually, an OCF might not necessarily even yield an ordinal notation, because there is no justification of the existence of a primitive recursive interpretation of the \(\in\)-relation. For example, googologists tend to "simplify" existing OCFs by dropping important conditions without understanding the reason why they are important. Since many complicated conditions in the original definitions are used in order to define the primitive recursive interpretations of the \(\in\)-relatinon, such poor droppings cause the lack of the primitive recursive interpretations of the \(\in\)-relations.

There are many OCFs in use, often similar to each other and easily confused (some even use the same symbols).

Bachmann's \(\psi\)

Main article: Bachmann's function

Heinz Bachmann's \(\psi\) function was the first true ordinal collapsing function.[1][2] It is somewhat cumbersome as it depends on fundamental sequences for all limit ordinals[2].

Rathjen suggests a "recast" of the system[3] as follows. Let \(\Omega\) be an uncountable ordinal such as \(\aleph_1\). Then define \(C^\Omega(\alpha, \beta)\) as the closure of \(\beta \cup \{0, \Omega\}\) under \(+, (\xi \mapsto \omega^\xi), (\xi \mapsto \psi_\Omega(\xi))_{\xi < \alpha}\), and \(\psi_\Omega(\alpha) = \min \{\rho < \Omega : C^\Omega(\alpha, \rho) \cap \Omega = \rho\}\).

\(\psi_\Omega(\varepsilon_{\Omega + 1})\) is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal[citation needed], the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory with axiom of infinity.

Feferman's \(\theta\)

Main article: Feferman's theta function

Feferman's \(\theta\)-functions constitute a hierarchy of single-argument functions \(\theta_\alpha: \text{On} \to \text{On}\) for \(\alpha \in \text{On}\).[4] It is often considered a two-argument function with \(\theta_\alpha(\beta)\) written as \(\theta\alpha\beta\). It is defined like so:

\begin{eqnarray*} C_0(\alpha, \beta) &=& \beta \cup \{0, \omega_1, \omega_2, \ldots, \omega_\omega\}\\ C_{n+1}(\alpha, \beta) &=& \{\gamma + \delta, \theta_\xi(\eta) | \gamma, \delta, \xi, \eta \in C_n(\alpha, \beta); \xi < \alpha\} \\ C(\alpha, \beta) &=& \bigcup_{n < \omega} C_n (\alpha, \beta) \\ \theta_\alpha(\beta) &=& \min\{\gamma | \gamma \not\in C(\alpha, \gamma) \wedge \forall \delta < \beta: \theta_\alpha(\delta) < \gamma\} \\ \end{eqnarray*}

Equivalently:

  • An ordinal \(\beta\) is considered \(\alpha\)-critical if it cannot be constructed with the following elements:
    • all ordinals less than \(\beta\),
    • all ordinals in the set \(\{0, \omega_1, \omega_2, \ldots, \omega_\omega\}\),
    • the operation \(+\),
    • applications of \(\theta_\xi\) for \(\xi < \alpha\).
  • \(\theta_\alpha\) is the enumerating function for all \(\alpha\)-critical ordinals.

The supremum of the countable ordinal expressed by the function is the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal \(\theta_{\varepsilon_{\Omega_\omega + 1}}(0)\),[4] Theorem 3.7 but an ordinal notation up to the ordinal associated to the function is unknown at least in this community.


Buchholz's \(\psi\)

Main article: Buchholz's function

Buchholz's \(\psi\) is a hierarchy of single-argument functions \(\psi_v: \text{On} \to \text{On}\) for \(v \leq \omega\), with \(\psi_v(\alpha)\) abbreviated as \(\psi_v\alpha\).[4] Define \(\Omega_0 = 1\) and \(\Omega_v = \aleph_v\) for \(v > 0\), and let \(P(\alpha)\) be the set of distinct terms in the Cantor normal form of \(\alpha\) (with each term of the form \(\omega^\xi\) for \(\xi \in \text{On}\)):

\begin{eqnarray*} C_v^0(\alpha) &=& \Omega_v\\ C_v^{n+1}(\alpha) &=& C_v^n(\alpha) \cup \{\gamma | P(\gamma) \subseteq C_v^n(\alpha)\} \cup \{\psi_v\xi | \xi \in \alpha \cap C_v^n(\alpha) \wedge \xi \in C_u(\xi) \wedge u \leq \omega\} \\ C_v(\alpha) &=& \bigcup_{n < \omega} C_v^n (\alpha) \\ \psi_v\alpha &=& \min\{\gamma | \gamma \not\in C_v(\alpha)\} \\ \end{eqnarray*}

The limit of this system is \(\psi_0(\varepsilon_{\Omega_\omega + 1})\), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal. It has a sophisticated extension called extended Buchholz's function (EBF for short) created by wiki user Denis Maksudov.

Madore's \(\psi\)

Main article: Madore's function

David Madore (under "Gro-Tsen" on Wikipedia) defined the following simpler variant of Buchholz's function as a demonstration of how ordinal collapsing functions work.[5] The popularity of the article led to widespread use of the modified function.

\begin{eqnarray*} C_0(\alpha) &=& \{0, 1, \omega, \Omega\}\\ C_{n+1}(\alpha) &=& \{\gamma + \delta, \gamma\delta, \gamma^{\delta}, \psi(\eta) | \gamma, \delta, \eta \in C_n (\alpha); \eta < \alpha\} \\ C(\alpha) &=& \bigcup_{n < \omega} C_n (\alpha) \\ \psi(\alpha) &=& \min\{\beta \in \Omega|\beta \notin C(\alpha)\} \\ \end{eqnarray*}

Informally:

  • \(C(\alpha)\) is the set of all ordinals constructible using only \(0\), \(1\), \(\omega\), \(\Omega\), and finite applications of the following functions: addition, multiplication, exponentiation, and \(\kappa \mapsto \psi(\kappa)\) (the latter only if \(\psi(\kappa)\) has yet been defined).
  • \(\psi(\alpha)\) is the smallest countable ordinal not in \(C(\alpha)\).

Chris Bird uses this function throughout his googological papers.[6]

Bird's \(\theta\)

Chris Bird devised the following shorthand for the extended (zero-indexed) Veblen function \(\varphi\):[7]

\[\theta(\Omega^{n - 1}a_{n - 1} + \cdots + \Omega^2a_2 + \Omega a_1 + a_0, b) = \varphi(a_{n - 1}, \ldots, a_2, a_1, a_0, b)\]

\(\theta(\alpha, 0)\) is abbreviated as \(\theta(\alpha)\). This function is only defined for arguments less than \(\Omega^\omega\), and its outputs are limited by the small Veblen ordinal. Nevertheless, in his articles, Bird erroneously uses \(\theta(\Omega^\omega)\) and higher values without properly defining the function. It means that he simply uses expressions like \(\theta(\Omega^{\omega})\) and \(\theta(\Omega^{\Omega})\) as shorthands of known ordinals.

Since this function is equivalent to Feferman's \(\theta\) function where both are defined, it may be that he was merely using an extension of this \(\theta\) function. It does not mean that this function is well-defined. Beginners should be careful if people use Bird's \(\theta\) function for arguments greater than or equal to \(\Omega^{\omega}\), because this function is ill-defined for ordinals greater than or equal to \(\Omega^{\omega}\).

Wilken's \(\vartheta\)

Wilken's \(\vartheta\) is more generic than other OCFs. Let \(\Omega_0\) be either \(1\) or a number of the form \(\varepsilon_\alpha\), let \(\Omega_1 > \Omega_0\) be an uncountable regular cardinal and for \(0 < i < \omega\) let \(\Omega_{i+1}\) be the successor cardinal to \(\Omega_i\). Then, for \(0 < n < \omega\) and \(0 \leq m < n\), define the following for \(\beta < \Omega_{m+1}\):[8]

\begin{eqnarray*} \Omega_m \cup \beta &\subseteq& C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \\ \xi, \eta \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) &\Rightarrow& \xi + \eta \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \\ \eta \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \cap \Omega_{k + 2} &\Rightarrow& \vartheta_k^n(\xi) \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \text{ for } m < k < n \\ \eta \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \cap \alpha &\Rightarrow& \vartheta_m^n(\xi) \in C_m^n(\alpha, \beta) \\ \vartheta_m^n(\alpha) &=& \min(\{\xi < \Omega_{m+1}|C_m^n(\alpha, \xi) \cap \Omega_{m+1} \subseteq \xi \wedge \alpha \in C_m^n(\alpha, \xi)\} \cup \{\Omega_{m+1}\}) \\ \end{eqnarray*}

\(n\) is needed to define the function, but the actual value of \(n\) does not affect the function's behavior. So, for example, \(\vartheta_0^1(\alpha) = \vartheta_0^2(\alpha) = \vartheta_0^3(\alpha) = \cdots\) So we can safely eliminate \(n\) and express the function using only two arguments \(\vartheta_m(\alpha)\).

Wilken and Weiermann's \(\bar\vartheta\)

Wilken and Weiermann's \(\bar\vartheta\) is closely related to Wilken's \(\vartheta\), and their paper closely analyzes the relationship between the two.[9] As before, let \(\Omega_0\) be either \(1\) or a number of the form \(\varepsilon_\alpha\), let \(\Omega_1 > \Omega_0\) be an uncountable regular cardinal and for \(0 < i < \omega\) let \(\Omega_{i+1}\) be the successor cardinal to \(\Omega_i\), and finally let \(\Omega_\omega = \sup_{i < \omega} \Omega_i\). For all \(\beta \leq \Omega_{i+1}\) define the following:

\begin{eqnarray*} \Omega_i \cup \beta &\subseteq& \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \beta) \\ \xi, \eta \in \bar{C}_i (\alpha, \beta) &\Rightarrow& \xi + \eta \in \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \beta) \\ j \leq i < \omega \wedge \xi \in \bar{C}_j(\xi, \Omega_{j + 1}) \cap \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \beta) \cap \alpha &\Rightarrow& \bar{\vartheta}_j(\xi) \in \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \beta) \\ \bar{\vartheta}_i(\alpha) &=& \min(\{\xi < \Omega_{i + 1} | \alpha \in \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \xi) \wedge \bar{C}_i(\alpha, \xi) \cap \Omega_{i + 1} \subseteq \xi\} \cup \{\Omega_{i + 1}\}) \\ \end{eqnarray*}

Weiermann's \(\vartheta\)

The \(\vartheta\) function has the advantage of having only a single argument, at the cost of some added complexity.[10] This OCF is similar in some ways to Bachmann's \(\psi\) and its recase by Rathjen.

\begin{eqnarray*} C_0(\alpha, \beta) &=& \beta \cup \{0, \Omega\}\\ C_{n+1}(\alpha, \beta) &=& \{\gamma + \delta, \omega^{\gamma}, \vartheta(\eta) | \gamma, \delta, \eta \in C_n (\alpha, \beta); \eta < \alpha\} \\ C(\alpha, \beta) &=& \bigcup_{n < \omega} C_n (\alpha, \beta) \\ \vartheta(\alpha) &=& \min \{\beta < \Omega | C(\alpha, \beta) \cap \Omega \subseteq \beta \wedge \alpha \in C(\alpha, \beta)\} \\ \end{eqnarray*}

Rathjen and Weiermann showed that \(\vartheta(\alpha)\) is defined for all \(\alpha < \varepsilon_{\Omega+1}\), but do not discuss higher values.

\(\vartheta\) follows the archetype of many ordinal collapsing functions — it is defined inductively with a "marriage" to the \(C\) function. Interpreting the equations:

  • \(C(\alpha, \beta)\) is the set of all ordinals constructible using only the following:
    • Zero, all ordinals less than \(\beta\), and \(\Omega\).
    • Finite applications of addition, \(\kappa \mapsto \omega^\kappa\), \(\kappa \mapsto \vartheta(\kappa)\) (the latter only if \(\vartheta(\kappa)\) has yet been defined).
  • \(\vartheta(\alpha)\) is the smallest ordinal \(\beta\) so that \(\alpha \in C(\alpha, \beta)\), and \(\beta\) is greater than all the countable ordinals in \(C(\alpha, \beta)\).


Jäger's \(\psi\)

Main article: Jäger's function

Jäger's \(\psi\) is a hierarchy of single-argument ordinal functions \(\psi_\kappa\) indexed by uncountable regular cardinals \(\kappa\) smaller than the least weakly Mahlo cardinal \(M_0\) introduced by German mathematician Gerhard Jäger in 1984[11]. It was developed on the base of Buchholz's approach.

Every \(\psi_\kappa\) is a function from \(M_0\) to \(\kappa\) which "collapses" the elements of \(M_0\) below \(\kappa\).

\(\kappa^{-}=0\) if \(\kappa=I_\alpha(0)\) for some \(\alpha \in \kappa\)

\(\kappa^{-}=I_\alpha(\beta)\) if \(\kappa=I_\alpha(\beta+1)\) for some \(\alpha,\beta \in \kappa\)

\(C_\kappa^0(\alpha) = \{\kappa^{-}\}\cup\kappa^{-}\)

For any \(n < \omega\), \(C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha) \subset M_0\) is the smallest set satisfying the following:

  1. The sum of any finitely many ordinals in \(C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\) belongs to \(C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha)\).
  2. For any \(\beta,\gamma\in C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\), \(\varphi_\beta(\gamma)\in C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha)\).
  3. For any \(\beta,\gamma\in C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\), \(I_\beta(\gamma)\in C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha)\).
  4. For any ordinal \(\gamma\) and uncountable regular cardinal \(\pi \in C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\), \(\gamma<\pi<\kappa\) implies \(\gamma\in C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha)\).
  5. For any \(\gamma \in \alpha \cap C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\) and uncountable regular cardinal \(\pi\in C_\kappa^n(\alpha)\), \(\gamma\in C_\pi(\gamma)\) implies \(\psi_\pi(\gamma)\in C_\kappa^{n+1}(\alpha)\).

\(C_\kappa(\alpha)=\bigcup\{C_\kappa^n(\alpha)|n<\omega\}\)

\(\psi_\kappa(\alpha)=\text{min}\{\xi \in \kappa|\xi\notin C_\kappa(\alpha)\}\)

It has a sophisticated simplification created by wiki user Denis Maksudov.[12]

Rathjen's \(\psi\)

Main article: Rathjen's psi function

Rathjen's \(\psi\) function is based on the least weakly Mahlo cardinal to create large countable ordinals.[13] A weakly Mahlo cardinal can be defined as a cardinal \(\text M\) such that all normal functions closed in \(\text M\) have a regular fixed point. He uses this to diagonalise over the weakly inaccessible hierarchy. It admits an associated ordinal notation \(T(\text{M})\) whose limit (i.e. ordinal type) is \(\psi_{\Omega}(\chi_{\varepsilon_{\text{M}+1}}(0))\), which is strictly greater than \(\textrm{PTO}(\textrm{KPM})\) and is strictly smaller than the limit of countable ordinals expressed by Rathjen's \(\psi\). For the full definition, see the main article.

Rathjen's \(\Psi\)

Main article: Rathjen's Psi function

Rathjen's \(\Psi\) function is based on the least weakly compact cardinal to create large countable ordinals.[14] A weakly compact cardinal can be defined as a cardinal \(\mathcal{K}\) such that it is \(\Pi_1^1\)-indescribable. He uses this to diagonalise over the weakly Mahlo hierarchy. The functions \(M^{\alpha}\), \(C(\alpha,\pi)\), \(\Xi(\alpha)\), and \(\Psi^{\xi}_{\pi}(\alpha)\) are defined in mutual recursion in the following way:

\(M^0=K\cap\text{Lim}\), where \(\text{Lim}\) denotes the class of limit ordinals.

For \(\alpha>0\), \(M^\alpha\) is the set of \(\pi<K\) such that \(\pi\) satisfies these 3 conditions:

  1. \(C(\alpha,\pi)\cap K = \pi\)
  2. \(\forall\xi\in C(\alpha,\pi) \cap \alpha, M^{\xi} \text{ stationary in }\pi\)
  3. \(\alpha\in C(\alpha,\pi)\)

\(C(\alpha,\beta)\) is the closure of \(\beta\cup\{0,K\}\) under addition, \((\xi,\eta)\mapsto\varphi(\xi,\eta)\), \(\xi\mapsto\Omega_\xi\) given \(\xi<K\), \(\xi\mapsto\Xi(\xi)\) given \(\xi<\alpha\), and \((\xi,\pi,\delta)\mapsto\Psi^\xi_\pi(\delta)\) given \(\xi\le\delta<\alpha\).

\(\Xi(\alpha)=\min(M^\alpha \cup\{K\})\).

For \(\xi\le\alpha\), \(\Psi^\xi_\pi(\alpha)=\min(\{\rho\in M^\xi\cap\pi \colon C(\alpha,\rho) \cap \pi = \rho \land \pi \land \alpha\in C(\alpha,\rho)\} \cup \{\pi\})\).

Duchhardt's \(\Psi\)

Christoph Duchhardt has created a 6-ary OCF \(\Psi\) using a \(\Pi_4\)-reflecting ordinal[15], and proved bounds on the proof-theoretic ordinal of KP set theory augmented by a certain \(\Pi_4\)-reflection principle.

Stegert's \(\Psi\)

Main article: Stegert's Psi function

As part of his 2010 Ph.D. dissertation, Jan-Carl Stegert introduced collapsing hierarchies \(\mathfrak{M}\) and two collapsing functions \(\Psi\), and developed a powerful ordinal notation based on the work of Rathjen.[16]

Arai's \(\psi\)

Arai introduced an OCF \(\psi\) based on first order reflection under an extension \(\textrm{ZFLK}_N\) of \(\textrm{ZFC}\) and a new simplified ordinal notation associated to it.[17] Here, \(N\) is a natural number greater than \(2\). Arai verified \(\psi_{\Omega_1}(\varepsilon_{\mathbb{K}+1})\) is the proof theoretic ordinal of \(\textrm{KP}\Pi_N\), where \(\mathbb{K}\) is the least \(\Pi_N\)-reflecting ordinal and \(\textrm{KP}\Pi_N\) is Kripke–Platek set theory for the \(\Pi_N\)-reflecting universe. This seems to be the current state of the art in the field of ordinal analysis.

References

  1. Bachmann, Heinz. "Die Normalfunktionen und das Problem der ausgezeichneten Folgen von Ordnungszahlen"Vierteljahrsschrift der Naturforschenden Gesellschaft in Zürich, vol. 95. Zürich: Orell Füssli Graphische Betriebe AG.. Retrieved 2014-08-29. Translation at https://arxiv.org/pdf/1903.04609.pdf
  2. 2.0 2.1 M. Rathjen, "A history of ordinal representations" (notes). Archived 2007-06-12.
  3. Rathjen, Michael. "The Art of Ordinal Analysis"
  4. 4.0 4.1 4.2 W. Buchholz, A New System of Proof-Theoretic Ordinal Functions, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 32, pp.195-207, (1986).
  5. "Ordinal Collapsing Function". Wikipedia. Retrieved 2014-08-29.
  6. Chris Bird, pers. comm
  7. Bird, Chris. "The Fast-Growing Hierarchy in Terms of Bird's Array Notations". Retrieved 2014-08-29.
  8. Wilken, Gunnar. "Ordinal arithmetic based on Skolem hulling". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. Retrieved 2014-09-21.
  9. Weiermann, Andreas and Wilken, Gunnar. "Ordinal arithmetic with simultaneously defined theta-functions". Wiley Online. Retrieved 2014-09-21.
  10. Rathjen, Michael and Weiermann, Andreas. "Proof Theoretic Investigations of Kruskal's Theorem"
  11. Jäger, M.. Arch. Math. Logik Grundlagenforsch (1984),24
  12. Traveling To The Infinity
  13. Rathjen, Michael. "Ordinal Notations Based on a Weakly Mahlo Cardinal", Archive for Mathematical Logic 29 (1990) 249--263.
  14. Rathjen, Michael. "Proof Theory of Reflection", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 68, 181--224 (1994).
  15. C. Duchhardt, Thinning operators and \(\Pi_4\)-reflection (2008)
  16. Stegert, Jan-Carl. "Ordinal proof theory of Kripke-Platek set theory augmented by strong reflection principles"
  17. T. Arai, A simplified ordinal analysis of first-order reflection

See also

Basics: cardinal numbers · ordinal numbers · limit ordinals · fundamental sequence · normal form · transfinite induction · ordinal notation
Theories: Robinson arithmetic · Presburger arithmetic · Peano arithmetic · KP · second-order arithmetic · ZFC
Model Theoretic Concepts: structure · elementary embedding
Countable ordinals: \(\omega\) · \(\varepsilon_0\) · \(\zeta_0\) · \(\eta_0\) · \(\Gamma_0\) (Feferman–Schütte ordinal) · \(\varphi(1,0,0,0)\) (Ackermann ordinal) · \(\psi_0(\Omega^{\Omega^\omega})\) (small Veblen ordinal) · \(\psi_0(\Omega^{\Omega^\Omega})\) (large Veblen ordinal) · \(\psi_0(\varepsilon_{\Omega + 1}) = \psi_0(\Omega_2)\) (Bachmann-Howard ordinal) · \(\psi_0(\Omega_\omega)\) with respect to Buchholz's ψ · \(\psi_0(\varepsilon_{\Omega_\omega + 1})\) (Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal) · \(\psi_0(\Omega_{\Omega_{\cdot_{\cdot_{\cdot}}}})\) (countable limit of Extended Buchholz's function)‎ · \(\omega_1^\mathfrak{Ch}\) · \(\omega_1^{\text{CK}}\) (Church-Kleene ordinal) · \(\omega_\alpha^\text{CK}\) (admissible ordinal) · recursively inaccessible ordinal · recursively Mahlo ordinal · reflecting ordinal · stable ordinal · \(\lambda,\zeta,\Sigma,\gamma\) (ordinals on infinite time Turing machine) · gap ordinal · List of countable ordinals
Ordinal hierarchies: Fast-growing hierarchy · Slow-growing hierarchy · Hardy hierarchy · Middle-growing hierarchy · N-growing hierarchy
Ordinal functions: enumeration · normal function · derivative · Veblen function · ordinal collapsing function · Bachmann's function · Madore's function · Feferman's theta function · Buchholz's function · Extended Buchholz's function · Jäger's function · Rathjen's psi function · Rathjen's Psi function · Stegert's Psi function
Uncountable cardinals: \(\omega_1\) · omega fixed point · inaccessible cardinal \(I\) · Mahlo cardinal \(M\) · weakly compact cardinal \(K\) · indescribable cardinal · rank-into-rank cardinal
Classes: \(V\) · \(L\) · \(\textrm{On}\) · \(\textrm{Lim}\) · \(\textrm{AP}\) · Class (set theory)

Community content is available under CC-BY-SA unless otherwise noted.